Coloured Bodies
The invention of sex may be a usefully considered to be a major landmark in the
development of modern organisms.
One of the reasons for this is that it may serve to mark the end of the
evolution of the main structure of the genetic code. Any major structural
changes in the genome are likely to render the organism which hosts them to be
incompatible with other members of its own species when it comes to mate with
them, rendering it sterile. Naturally, any sexual organism incapable of
interbreeding with its fellows is genetically doomed.
If a new variation upon a genetic mechanism is good enough that its organisms
can afford to abandon the rest of the gene pool in which they find themselves,
then it may prevail. Otherwise the majority are likely to win out over any
innovative improvements in the genetic system. Sex could thus be described as a
heavy subsequently constructed structure, built on top of the genetic mechanism
which tends to fix it in position.
The above description applies to small, gradual changes in the genetic
structure, but is not relevant to theories of genetic takeover of the kind
described by A. G.
Cairns-Smith, which remain possible for as long as a superior genetic
substrate can be envisaged.
Having mentioned Cairns-Smith's work,
another of his metaphors seems appropriate to the discussion. He describes the
lock in
phenomena concisely, using the metaphor of building a
stone arch. This is a classic metaphor illustrating that the initial stages of
final constructions may be best seen by envisaging preliminary supporting
structures; in the example of the stone arch, this may be a mound of earth. If
the mound of earth is then removed, the arch becomes suddenly brittle and
locked in
to a state where all the stones depend on each other.
Once this dropping away of preliminary structures has occurred, there is often
no going back, even if the resulting construction contains aspects which are no
longer appropriate to the uses to which it is being put.
It seems unfortunate that Cairns-Smith's work
has not found a wider audience within the A-life community. One problem may be
that a well known A-life enthusiast
Stuart Kauffman has
proposed a conflicting theory of the origin of life to the one Cairns-Smith
proposes, involving autocatalytic sets. The author believes that this barrier
may eventually be resolved by problems within the autocatalytic theory.
Cairns-Smith's own critique of models of chemical evolution
seems to be applicable, as autocatalytic sets would seem to have what
Cairns-Smith describes as a low ceiling
in terms of information
storage. This, if true, would prevent them from being considered seriously as
candidates for the first genetic material.
Turning back to chromosomes, meiosis will now be examined. There seems to be
some control by the chromosomes over the details of how meiosis operates. For
example, some parts of the genome are more sexy than others. Different parts of
chromosomes also have different baseline mutation rates. However, these effects
provide only a very minor structural element to meiosis. Apart from the near
immunity of that genetic wasteland, the Y chromosome, there are no parts of the
genome which are treated with additional respect by the process.
Meiosis' lack of discrimination may be an aspect of its even-handedness. If the
meiotic process can be influenced by a particular gene in a manner that makes
that gene more likely than its alles to find its way into gametes, then that
gene will come to dominate, even it it has other severe side-effects on
individuals who bear it. This kind of gene is often referred to as an outlaw
gene. There is subsequent pressure on meiosis from the other genes in the
organism which all suffer from the adverse effects of outlaw genes. It has been
theorised that under some conditions the outlaws are fairly effectively
suppressed. It may be that the form of the suppression forces meiosis to be
simple, as any structural complexity offers outlaws opportunities for subverting
the process to their own ends.
The some conditions
under which the outlaws are suppressed are
theorised to be as follows:
Outlaws that act by subverting meiosis or around the point of conception are
known as segregation distorters. They may act at other points in the lifecycle
of the organism, as in the example of a behaviour pattern, influenced by a gene
on the Y-chromosome, causing fathers to invest more resources in bringing up
sons than daughters.
Outlaw genes not only help themselves to a larger slice of the genetic pie
than they would normally receive, they usually help their chromosomal
neighbours too. Sometimes (depending on how the outlaw pursues its aims) the
entire chromosome containing the gene is helped. If an organism has a large
number of chromosomes then a larger proportion of the organism's genes suffer
as a result of their association with the outlaw than would if the organism
had fewer chromosomes. These are more likely to act in unison to suppress the
effects of the outlaw genes, than if there are, for example, only two
chromosome pairs, in which case one of them may want the outlaw to succeed
because its genes will directly be levered into the next generation by the
outlaw's mechanism. It will try to block any suppression effects which the
other chromosome pair would like to impose on the outlaw.
If this reasoning is correct then it follows that multiple chromosomes and sex
go together. No suggestion is being made here as to which of these adaptations
came first. There may be other pressures favouring multiple chromosomes
(including structural and engineering considerations). However, organisms using
sex with a low chromosome count may need some variations in its style of
meiotic division if they are not to become prey to outlaw genes.
The reason for interest here in the structure of chromosomes is as follows.
Genes display associations with other genes in the genome, in that some groups
of genes are more likely than others to find themselves sharing bodies in
offspring. These genes are described as being linked to one another.
The mechanism behind linkage is very simple: genes that are on the same
chromosome are linked roughly in proportion to the distance they are from
one another along it. This distance is related to the probability that
meiosis or mutation will act to cleave the two genes involved. Genes on
different chromosomes are considered not to be linked at all - their
probabilities of making their way into a body in the next generation
are normally not connected at all.
Linkage is important. Even in asexual organisms where rapid genetic shuffling
is not the norm, it may play some role. Characters which are developmentally
related or inter-dependant would gravitate towards close linkage. Genes that
need one another for their mutual well being would be inclined to find
themselves next door to one another. Within linkage groups, genes would tend to
cooperate more with their neighbours than with the rest of their particular
genome when they encounter copies of them in other bodies. Recognising a copy
of your close neighbour out in the world may be exactly equivalent to
recognising a copy of yourself.
The means by which genes are brought together is of course natural selection,
but of a slightly unusual type. Usually selection may be thought of acting on
the phenotypes of organisms, but in any individual organism genetic linkage
displays no obvious signs of its effects. It is only when the organism
reproduces that some important groups may be separated if they are not closely
linked. The selection pressures may be thought of as being towards
evolvability, and away from a tendency towards rapid genetic decay in
descendants. The recognition of the existence of such selection pressures is
not yet widespread. For a justification of the plausability of such selection
pressures readers are hereby referred to the chapter titled
Kaleidoscopic Embryos
in
Richard Dawkins' recent book,
Climbing Mount Improbable
.
Linkage comes to follow and mirror the structure of the organism. This is not
meant literally - in the sense that genes associated with different adult bodily
parts would like to form an isomorphic structure on the genome - but giving due
consideration to the developmental history of the organism. In the complex and
mysterious growth processes of embryology, genes can be seen as waltzing with
other genes, and their partners tend to become their eternal soulmates.
The main point to be made here is that distance is a very crude one-dimensional
symmetrical measure. If an organism could have multi-dimensional asymmetrical,
conditional, with complex interdependencies as relationships portrayed by links,
then it would benefit in that the complex relationships and dependencies
between genes in embryological processes could be captured more clearly.
In the additional organism, genes may ony be more or less strongly linked to
to one another. It would seem desirable to be able to represent more complex
relationships between genes. For example, the relationshoip: "Gene A
helps Gene B if in the presence of Gene C, but otherwise it hinders it", is not
a relationship which can be easily expressed in terms of simple linkage. Such
relationships between genes most certainly exist and have been tracked in the
studies of genetically inherited diseases.
Tree-shaped chromosomes are referred to here. This is for a number of reasons.
Heirarchical trees are familiar data structures to many. They are easy to
implement on existing computers. A simple representation can be imagined as a
one-dimensional string of characters using nested brackets to indicate the
branching depth.
There is no need to imagine anything as complex as branching in the physical
DNA used to encode genes. A simple one-dimensional structure may be used, but
it should contain markers (serving the same function as the brackets referred
to above) which encode information relating to the tree structure, and which
influence meiosis. It is easy to imagine the sexual process as being
represented by a pruning and grafting process between chromosomes.
I do not claim that tree-shaped
is in any sense an optimal
structure and it may be preferable to consider genes as being related to groups
of linkage properties in an orthodox object-oriented manner.
There seem to be two main problems with the idea as it has been presented.
Bearing in mind the existing state of the genetic substrate, the advantage of
having a better map between genetic and developmental/phenotypic structure may
be counterbalanced by a corresponding high cost of implementation. The existing
genome is one-dimensional and complex links would probably have to be
represented physically on it in some manner, and then read in the process of
meiosis. I have mentioned above that the redundancy of the existing genetic
code could provide one way of coding such information. Another method (which I
have been advised is already used) would be to provide marker strings of DNA
which act as cutting marks for particular enzymes.
Also, this kind of selective meiosis would be just the kind of mechanism outlaw
genes would love to get their hands on in pursuit of their own subversive
goals. This would have to be guarded against. In the same way that splitting
the genome into unlinked independant sections may help suppress the action of
outlaw genes in the existing system, exactly the same strategy could reasonably
be expected to reduce their effects in an organism with tree-shaped
chromosomes.
Another possibility might be to store information about structure and linkage
non-locally. This would certainly prevent any linkage effects between the
markers and the genes which they are marking, but it is no longer clear how
this linkage information could then be inherited with the genes which they
are marking. Without this, the linkage information would not be useful.
Between them, the two disadvantages mentioned above may contribute to the
apparent absence of such geometries from modern organisms.
Naturally the two problems described above apply mainly to small variations on
the existing system. Messianic A-life heads - who feel as though they have an
opportunity to start from scratch - may wish to avoid constraining themselves by
such considerations.